Outline:
1st Introduction
2nd The basic problem
3rd The short-term market law
4th The role of the rent in value assessment
5th The role of the capital in value assessment
6th Can different labour qualities be converted into normal working hours?
7th Criticism of the Ricardian Theory of Value
8th Long-term development of a national economy
1st Introduction
In the previous chapter, I already
pointed out that at the end of the 18th century, economic theories were
developed mainly in England, but also on the European continent, which on the
one hand tried to prove that a free market economy leads to essentially better
results than a state-controlled mercantilist economy, but which on the other
hand also tried to describe the functioning of a market economy.
The first approach has already
been described in the previous chapter and was referred to as liberalism. This
approach is normative, it aims to show which economic system will increase the
welfare of a population most effectively. The second approach shall be
described here as Classicism, its concern is of an explicative nature, it is
not primarily intended to advertise a free market economy, but to show which
laws a market economy is subject to. Only with this second approach we want to
deal in this chapter.
However, I had already
mentioned that the individual economic authors can by no means be strictly
distinguished between these two groups. For example, Adam Smith, who was at the
centre of the previous chapter and is considered to be the founder of the newer
national economy, has contributed significantly to both the development of
liberal ideas as well as to the formulation of an explicative market theory. He
is therefore mentioned in literature both as a representative of old liberalism
and as an early classicist.
In the previous chapter we
have dealt solely with Adam Smith's liberal ideas and in this chapter we will abstain to include Adam Smith's contribution
to the classical market theory.
The focus of this chapter
shall be set solely on the remarks of David Ricardo, who has brought the
considerations, which were treated already by Adam Smith, to a certain
culmination and conclusion. It is precisely for these reasons that the
literature distinguishes between the optimistic, early classical view of Adam
Smith and the late classical, markedly pessimistic view of David Ricardo and
Robert Malthus.
David Ricardo lived from
1772-1823 and became known primarily for his two major works 'The High Price of
Bullion, a Proof of the Depreciation of Bank Notes' (1809) and 'On the
Principles of Political Economy and Taxation' (1817). Among his most important
contributions to economic theory are the foundation of the classical labour
value theory, the finding that the monetary value can only be guaranteed by a
central bank monopoly, and his theory of comparative costs, in which he proves
that in general all countries can benefit from international trade.
The necessary temporal
limitation of a chapter in this seminar even makes it necessary, even within
the total contribution of David Ricardo, to limit oneself to a single but quite
central topic of classical theory and to deal only with David Ricardo's theory
of value. In this, we will mainly limit ourselves to the works of Ricardo. The
theses of Robert Malthus are included in this presentation only insofar as they
are necessary for understanding the Ricardian value system. Ricardo himself has
taken up some of Malthus' ideas. Ricardo's contribution to the theory of
foreign trade will then be discussed only in the second part of this lecture.
2nd
The basic problem
In this chapter we will
therefore deal exclusively with the value problem and its solution by David
Ricardo. We must clarify to which determinants the value of a good must be traced
back, which value the individual goods obtain, on what it depends if the value
of the good X turns out to be greater than the value of the good Y.
In this context, the first
thing we have to realise is that the value of
individual goods plays a central role in the question of which goods are
produced. Economic activity is always necessary when there is a shortage, that
is, when the available resources are not sufficient to
produce all the goods for which there is a demand. Here, it must be determined
which products should be produced in this case and to what extent. In economic
theory, this problem is called the problem of allocation, the distribution of
scarce resources to the individual possible types of use.
In this context, it must be
assumed implicitly that the respective predominant technology does indeed allow
us to use one and the same resource for different purposes. It is only because
several purposes of the scarce resources are known that the problem arises at
all, to which purposes scarce resources should be distributed.
The answer can only be that in
each case the kind of allocation to the individual possible types of use is
desired, which gives the highest possible benefit for a given resource stock
and a given technology.
Now, it is decisive that the
values that goods acquire on a free market play a central role in solving this
allocation problem in a market economy. It is the price ratios which direct the
resources to the individual types of use. Let us illustrate this relationship with
an example.
For the sake of simplicity,
let us assume that we only know two types of use, that by using the available
resources only the goods X and/or goods Y can be produced. We assume here, that
a certain distribution of resources to both goods has taken place previously,
e.g. half of the resources are used for goods X and half for goods Y.
We now want to assume that the
needs of consumers have changed in such a way that they achieve a greater
benefit if they consume much more of good X and accordingly less of good Y.
Consumers will therefore demand more of good X and less of good Y.
In free markets, this shift in
demand now automatically causes that the price of X rises, but that the price
of Y falls. This shift in value relations causes entrepreneurs to produce more
of good X and less of good Y, and this is because they earn more from the
production of good X due to the changed prices of goods. Thus, the price ratio
has ultimately controlled the allocation of resources.
The classical theory of value
now strives to clarify the question of what the value depends on in the sense
of a price that is valid in the long term. Firstly, it is important here that
the term 'value' in the context of the old-classical doctrine always refers to
the long-term price only. The problem of short-term price fluctuations
is only marginally approached in the classical literature and follows
completely different rules.
Secondly, when the classics
talk about values, they are always only interested in the relations of
long-term prices, but not in the absolute level of a price. This is because
it depends on the values of the goods, which goods are produced in which quantities
and that here only the structure of the prices, i.e. the price ratio, is
decisive. If e.g. the absolute price of both goods X and Y doubles and
therefore the ratio of the prices to each other has not changed, there is no
reason to change the allocation of resources to the two goods.
In the answer to the question
of which determinants ultimately determine the value of a good, David Ricardo
follows the view common at his time, which is also found with Adam Smith and
which traces the value of a good back to the cost sum necessary to produce it.
It is important to note that it depends on how many costs are necessary
with a given technology, not necessarily what costs are actually incurred.
An entrepreneur who is not up to date with the technology and therefore has
higher costs than his competitor will still not be able to obtain a higher
price on the free market than his competitor. The price that prevails is always
determined by the competitor who succeeds in offering a certain good at the
lowest cost.
However, David Ricardo is not satisfied
with this answer. He clearly recognises - and this is his actual contribution
to classical value theory - that this answer could only satisfy if there was
only one cost factor present. But in reality, it must
be assumed that several cost factors must be applied in the production of most
goods. Production usually requires a certain piece of land, i.e. the production
factor land, furthermore the use of capital for the purchase of machines, and furthermore
quite different qualities of labour.
If we now must assume several
factor types, we will only come to a satisfactory result if we are able to
indicate the role of the individual cost types for the total cost level. Let us
illustrate this correlation again with an example:
For a certain good X, 100
working hours and interest in the amount of 100 GE (monetary units) would be
required. For another good, on the other hand, only 30 working hours would be
needed, but due to a mechanisation of production, 400 GE would be needed. So which good has a higher value? In fact, this question
depends on the value of an hour of work compared to a GE of capital. The value
problem of a good is traced back to a value problem of the individual cost factors.
Only if I know the reasons on which the price ratio of wages and interest
depends, I can make a binding statement about the value of a good. A value
problem (that of the goods) is traced back to another value problem (that of
the production factors), the problem is not solved, an unknown is explained
with another unknown.
David Ricardo has clearly
recognised this problem; his effort is to trace back the individual cost types
to a single cost element. In this respect, he endeavours to exclude both the rent
as well as the price of land, and further to exclude capital investment as
possible determinants of the value of a good. Furthermore, according to a given
technical relation, the individual labour input is converted into units of
normal working hours (standardised working hours). Finally, it is possible to
indicate how many normal working hours are required to produce a good; and the
ratio of these working hours in the use of two goods to each other then finally
determines the value relation of both goods.
3rd The short-term market law
Although David Ricardo's theory
of value focuses on the long-term prices of goods, we want to begin the report with
briefly outlining the ideas of the classicists, above all John Stuart Mill,
about the determinants of short-term price changes.
Basically, the old classics
anticipated the neoclassical market theory in this point in its essential
features. Accordingly, short-term prices are corrected whenever supply and
demand diverge. If supply rises above demand, the price falls; the suppliers fear
to be stuck with their goods at the previous price and are therefore willing to
offer discounts. Now this price reduction has two effects: on the one hand, the
demand increases, on the other hand, the supply decreases with the consequence that
supply and demand come closer together and finally, if the price is
sufficiently reduced, they correspond to each other.
The same applies mutatis
mutandis if demand exceeds supply initially. In this case, prices rise in the
short term, as this time the demand side fears that they will not be able to
benefit at previous prices. But if the price rises, demand falls and supply
rises, both thus approaching each other again, until a new equilibrium price
has been reached finally at which supply and demand correspond precisely.
These considerations, however,
only refer to the short-term market reactions, which are of less interest to
David Ricardo.
4th
The role of the rent in value assessment
We now turn to Ricardo's
reasoning that eventually it is the number of required standard working hours
that determines the long-term value of a good. Let us begin with the thesis
that the rent cannot determine the value of a good.
David Ricardo assumes a
situation where the demand for agricultural products (and it is on these
products that the present problem is illustrated) is initially so low that the
respective most fertile soils are sufficient to
satisfy the demand.
For whatever reason, e.g. due
to an increase in population, the demand for soil products was now increasing
to such an extent that the most fertile soils were no longer sufficient
to meet the demand for products. The price of goods is rising. Farmers are
therefore induced to cultivate less fertile soil, which of course means that
the cost per unit of product is higher in the case of poorer-quality soil. But
these additional products will only be offered on the market if the costs are
also covered on the worst-quality soil, in other words if prices have risen in
proportion to the increase in costs. However, since identical products achieve
a uniform price on the market, the owners of the better-quality soil receive a
price that is higher than their costs, in other words they receive a rent.
This rent was thus - according
to David Ricardo conclusions - a consequence of the price increase of soil
products. But what was the consequence of a price increase could not simultaneously
be the cause of this price. Thus Ricardo - or at least it seems so - has eliminated
the rent as a possible determinant of a long-term price of goods.
5th The role of the capital in value assessment
Let us now turn to the question
why even interest on capital cannot be included - according to Ricardo's
opinion - in the circle of determinants of the value of goods. David Ricardo
assumes in his reasoning that a production lasts one period at a time. Since
the employed workers must be paid immediately, but since the sale proceeds are
only available after the completion of the product, the entrepreneur is forced
to take out a loan in order to pay and employ the workers in the first period.
If we now assume that all
workers are employed for the same wage, the required credit amount, which
corresponds to the wage costs, corresponds exactly to the number of hours
worked. Thus, two enterprises employing the same number of workers (with the
same number of working hours per day) must obtain the same amount of credit and
pay the same amount of interest at the same interest rates. Conversely, if
twice as many working hours must be performed in the production of good X than
in the production of good Y, then the interest paid in the production of good X
is also twice as high as in the production of good Y.
In other words, the incurred
capital costs always represent a certain percentage of the labour costs that is
the same for all productions and thus change the absolute value, but not the
value relations between the individual goods. But since David Ricardo is only
interested in the value relations, since they alone determine the management of
production, David Ricardo seems to have succeeded in eliminating the capital
costs as determining factor of the value of goods.
We want to keep in mind that
David Ricardo assumed in his reasoning that the time period required for
production is identical for all products and covers one period. In the
criticism of the Ricardian theory of value more below, we will see that this
assumption is very problematic, but that the result was obtained only under
this assumption.
6th Can different labour qualities be converted into normal working hours?
If we follow David Ricardo's
reasoning, then remains only the problem that in almost all productions
employees of the most different quality (unskilled workers, semi-skilled
workers, skilled workers) are employed, so that initially, even if we only
accept employees as determining factors for the value of a good, still remains
a multitude of different production factors of different quality, so that it
continues to be unclear how the values of the individual work qualities are to
be classified, so that then a uniform standard for the working hour is found.
David Ricardo has indeed accepted
this fact of a multitude of different work qualities. He was of the opinion,
however, that there are purely technical relations, which remain quite constant
in the short term, which permit the conversion of one working hour of a
qualified employee into normal working hours. For example, one working hour of
a foreman could correspond to 3 standardised working hours.
The crucial point in this
procedure is that David Ricardo was convinced that the addressed ratio of the
individual working hours to each other presented by no means an economic
problem. In this respect, a value ratio is always an economic problem and not a
purely technical problem when this ratio depends on the scarcity of the
individual labour force.
If we follow David Ricardo's reasoning,
then at the end of this chain of evidence there is a single production factor:
the standardised working hour. Then we are actually able
to indicate the number of standardised and necessary working hours for the
production of each good and thus to determine exactly how the values of the
individual goods relate to each other. Assuming the validity of these steps of
evidence, David Ricardo has obviously succeeded to solve the problem of the
classical objective value theory. Even when in reality a
large number of different production factors is almost always required
for the production of a good, it is possible to determine the value of each
good by specifying the number of standardised working hours.
7th Criticism of the Ricardian Theory of Value
Let us now ask about the
possible criticism of this value theory. Let us begin with the first step of
the reasoning: with the proof that, as being a result of a price increase, rents
could not at simultaneously be the determining factor of that same price.
Reminder: According to David
Ricardo, there is an increase in the demand for agricultural products and this
leads to price increases due to scarcity of the goods. This reasoning can be
accepted in any case.
In a second step, the attempt
by the suppliers to meet this increased demand by expanding production results
in the necessity to cultivate soil of inferior quality. This assertion can also
be accepted.
On free markets, products of
the same quality also achieve a uniform price, regardless of whether different
unit costs are incurred in production in the individual enterprises. This
statement also complies with the currently valid theory.
Furthermore, the products
which cause higher unit costs due to inferior quality of the soil are only
produced and offered on the market if the price at least corresponds to the
unit costs. This statement can certainly
not be criticised either.
The same price at unequal unit
costs ultimately leads automatically to the fact that the owners of the better
soils receive a rent.
Therefore, it seems that the
attempt to remove the rent from the circle of determinants of a price was
successfully conducted by David Ricardo. The question arises, however, as to
why this line of argument has validity only for soil and thus for soil rents.
Does this reasoning not apply actually to all
conceivable production factors? The fact that a proportion of cultivated soils
receive rents is obviously solely because soils have different qualities. But
does this not apply to the other production factors, too?
Let us review this question
for the capital. As we know, we must reckon quite often with the fact that
committing capital is sometimes quite risky. In these cases, the market grants
risk compensation to the providers of capital in the form of higher interest
rates. In this context, it can be affirmed that if the risk taken is higher,
the interest rate will be higher. On the other side, however, there are also
capital investments that involve almost no risk. Thus, we can see that the
quality of the capital also varies and that therefore different interest rates
must be paid for different capital.
Although it seems that the
quality of the soils was of a different character than the quality of the
capital. The fact that soil rents are granted is due to the condition of the
soil, that is, the characteristics of the offered production factor. But
that capital shows a different quality is based on the fact that
enterprises, i.e. the demanders of this production factor, are willing
to take a different risk.
Nevertheless, there is one
thing in common. Enterprises that demand capital need capital of different
quality depending on the risk taken. An entrepreneur who wants to set up an
investment with a very high risk will also need investors who are willing to take
a higher risk. It is this different willingness of the suppliers of
capital that determines the quality of the granted capital.
With regard
to the production factor labour, David Ricardo of
course assumes different qualities also. And he certainly also assumes that
employees who show above-average quality also receive above-average wages. Why
should we not be able to say here that the qualitatively better employees
receive a quality rent?
If, however, the rent concept
proven for soils by David Ricardo can de facto be applied to every conceivable
production factor, all factors are catapulted out of the circle of possible
determinants, with the result that the value of goods remains undetermined as
long as one wants to derive the value of goods objectively from the factor
input.
This is precisely the answer
of the Viennese School, the first variant of neoclassical theory. The value of
a good can never be ascribed to the use of a factor of production alone;
rather, it is determined solely by the benefit that the end consumer derives
from the consumption of a good.
A slightly different answer
finds the Cambridge School, the third variant of the neoclassical theory. These
representatives of the Neoclassicism assume that the value of a good is
determined by supply and demand, that a change in the supply of a production
factor as well as a change in demand can cause a change in the value of goods.
In a second step, let us now
ask to what extent David Ricardo's attempt to remove the cost of capital from
the list of possible determinants is convincing. We have already pointed out at
the reasoning above, that David Ricardo succeeded in removing the cost of
capital from the list of possible determinants of the value of goods only
because he implicitly assumed that all enterprises needed a single period for
their production. This assumption is certainly not in accordance with reality.
In reality,
we have to assume that production usually
requires several periods due to roundabout methods of production and that the
duration of these roundabout production methods differs from product to
product.
But if this is the case, we
can no longer consider the capital costs to be the same percentage of labour
costs everywhere. Let us consider an example:
We assume that an enterprise A
produces quite labour-intensively, that 10 employees are employed for a total
of 100 working hours - already converted into standardised working hours - and
that the production from the beginning to the end is just one period. Before
starting production, the entrepreneur is forced to take out a loan that is just
enough to pay off the workers. For the sake of simplicity, we will assume that
there are no other costs apart from labour costs, e.g. raw materials are
processed which are already in the possession of the entrepreneur.
We now assume a second
enterprise B, which, in contrast to enterprise A, produces very
capital-intensively, whereby we again want to assume here that the raw
materials required for production are already in the possession of this
enterprise. Furthermore, it is assumed for the sake of simplicity, that the
machines required for the production of the end
product are produced in this enterprise itself. Again, 10 workers would be
employed with a total of 100 standardised working hours.
The production of the end product now requires two periods for the entire
production process, whereby initially only the required machine is produced in
the first period, with the help of which the end product is then produced in
the second period. The roundabout production method therefore comprised two
periods for enterprise B, but only one period for enterprise A.
These assumptions now result
in enterprise A requiring a loan that is enough to allow the employees to work
a total of 100 hours and to pay them immediately. Since the interest rate was
3%, would be added to the labour costs another 3% of labour costs as interest
costs on the total cost sum.
Enterprise B, by contrast,
requires a loan that is enough to employ the workers for two periods. If the
interest rate is the same, this means that interest costs must be added to the
labour costs, which do not amount to 3% but 6% of the total labour costs.
This shows that the value sums
of both products are not only increased in their absolute level by
including the capital costs, but that the value relations change as well. This
proves that when considering production periods of different lengths, the value
relations between two goods are determined not only by the number of necessary
and standardised working hours, but also by the level of the capital costs. The
attempt to reduce the number of types of production factors to one has thus
failed.
Let us finally turn to David
Ricardo's third step, proving that the multitude of different qualities of work
can be ascribed to a standardised quality of work. As shown, David Ricardo
tries to solve this task by ascribing the wage differences of different work
qualities to purely technical determinants, which can be regarded furthermore
as constant at least in the short term and thus be regarded as given.
Just this assumption must be
doubted, however. In reality, these value relations in
wages are of an economic nature and thus are problem variables and not data
variables as assumed by Ricardo. We speak of economic problems here whenever
the value relations depend on the scarcity of these factors. And indeed, we have to assume that scarcity relations are involved in
determining the value relations of the different qualities of work. Let us
illustrate this thesis with a simple example:
We assume a small enterprise
which employs 10 unskilled workers for the production of
a handcraft product. The workers comply with the standardised quality of work
and additionally need a foreman who supervises the hand movements of the
workers. We would also like to assume that in the past, the foreman was
traditionally paid twice the wages of the unskilled workers. Although it is
incomprehensible to me how one should be able to assume that for technical
reasons the supervision of the workers is worth just twice as much as the
execution of the work, we still want to assume that on the basis of such
notions the foreman's salary was fixed previously.
We now want to assume that the
employment relationship of the foreman is discontinued, e.g. because he
retires, so that the enterprise must hire a new foreman. We also want to assume
that foremen have become very scarce as a result of a booming economy and that
the enterprise can therefore only employ a new foreman on the condition that he
is paid not twice but three times the basic salary of the other workers
employed.
In this example, the value
relations of the individual work qualities are clearly determined by scarcity
relations and it will have to be conceded that even in reality it must be
reckoned with this possibility (the scarcity of certain skilled workers) very
often. But then David Ricardo has also missed his aim in this third step of
evidence: he has again tried to explain an unknown (namely the value of a good)
by another unknown (namely the value of a work quality among several) and thus
missed his aim. The problem would only be solved if he had succeeded in clearly
ascribing the respective wage relations to data quantities which do not require
any further explanation.
Let us try to summarise these three
points of criticism in David Ricardo's reasoning: David Ricardo did not succeed in reducing the multitude of actually
existing types of production factors to a single variable. Thus, it remains
that the attempt of the representatives of the classicism, to ascribe the value
of a good to objective quantities, namely to the necessary unit costs of a
good, has failed.
Now this certainly does not
mean that David Ricardo's theory of value should be thrown on the rubbish heap
of teaching history. It remains the merit that David Ricardo is almost the only
one of the classical scientists to have succeeded in recognising the problem of
every objective theory of value. It was a great achievement to have correctly
recognised that ascribing the values of individual goods to the necessary unit
costs can only be satisfactory if it can be proven that a single homogeneous
production factor alone determines the value of a good.
It is said that the correct
recognition of a problem is already half the solution, but it is just only the
one half. At the solution of the correctly identified problem one of the famous
errors of reasoning in the history of national economics is present. But even
here, the way in which David Ricardo proceeded in order to finally attribute
the multitude of production factors that determine the value of goods to one
determining factor must be described as markedly brilliant.
Ricardo's error was firstly due to
the fact that he failed to recognise that the reasoning for the elimination of
the factor soil could basically be applied to any factor of production;
secondly, that he apparently proceeded from the assumption that the differences
in the length of production periods were irrelevant to his reasoning; and finally
that he thirdly overlooked the fact that the wage relations between the
individual qualities of work very often depend on scarcity and thus on a
problem variable that has to be clarified within the framework of an economic
science.
8th Long-term development of a national economy
Our model of the Ricardian
value theory discussed so far was static and stationary. It was static because
we limited ourselves to the value that a good will achieve in the long run. We
did not ask in which way and in which period of time
such a value is achieved in practice.
The concept was moreover
stationary, because we were only asking what value a good would achieve in the
present world. We have not yet examined what changes in these values can be
expected in the long term, whether we can assume a growth rate in these values
and whether these values are heading towards a certain limit in the very long
term.
David Ricardo has also
reflected on these dynamic aspects of a value theory in his work, and at the
end of this chapter we will briefly introduce this dynamic model of Ricardo and
then examine it critically. In doing so, Ricardo also draws on the theory of
population developed by Robert Malthus.
As is well known, Robert
Malthus had made a very pessimistic prognosis about population development and
the possibility of adequate economic growth. In his popular version, this
theory states that the population has the tendency to grow in the sense of a
geometric series, while the food supply can only grow in the sense of an
arithmetic series.
We always speak of a geometric
series when the respective numbers correspond to a scheme as follows:
The values of a certain variable
- in the example of the population theory of Malthus: the population - thus
double from period to period, or in general, the values of the respective next
period result from the value of the previous period, in which this is
multiplied by a constant variable (in our example with size 2).
By contrast, we speak of an
arithmetic series whenever the respective numbers correspond to the following
scheme:
The values of the variables mentioned
here (the food margin in our example) increase from period to period by one
unit or generally by a constant absolute amount.
Behind the statement that the
population is developing in the sense of a geometric series, there is of course
no real, empirically verifiable assumption, unless the exact length of the
period is given. If the population is growing, at some point it will have
doubled, which may be the case in ten years, then we would assume rapid,
frightening growth of the population; but that may also only happen after 10
000 years, then we would assume very moderate growth of the population.
A certain informative content
is given to Malthus' thesis about population growth, though, already when the
length of the periods remains identical always.
The further statement that the
food scope grows only in the sense of an arithmetic series is derived from the
law of diminishing marginal revenue of the soil, which had been developed by
both David Ricardo and Robert Malthus.
According to this, the soil
revenue can be increased by cultivating more soil that has been uncultivated or
by switching to a more intensive type of cultivation. However, the increase in
revenue decreases with each increase in the area of cultivated soil or with
each increase in intensification. This increase in revenue is known as marginal
revenue.
The reason for this decline in
marginal revenue in the case of an expansion of the cultivated soil area is
that more and more soil must be used that is less suitable for cultivation.
Initially, the best quality soils are selected, but the more is produced, the
more soils must be used which are of inferior quality.
If one chooses the way of an
intensification in order to increase the total revenue, the intensification
leads to decreasing marginal revenues, because a multitude of factors (of the
soil conditions) is involved in every development and because in the course of
the intensification the optimal composition of the individual factors is more
and more abandoned.
If we now assume that the population is
growing and that the marginal revenue of the land is decreasing more and more
due to the expansion of soil production, a regularity is developing, which is
shown in the following diagram:
On the abscissa we want to draw
the size of the population and, derived from this, also the number of workers
employed in agriculture, whereas on the ordinate we draw the marginal revenue
of the soil.
We assume a point in time when
the size of the population was still relatively small and, for example, was
equivalent to size B1. Due to the smaller population, it was still possible to
cultivate only the best quality soils, with the consequence that only a low rent
was achieved, the quality of the cultivated soils did not yet show any
considerable differences.
The surface below the dividing
line for the rent represents the total revenue of the production after
deduction of the rent. This remaining sum is now divided between entrepreneurs
and capital providers on the one hand and workers on the other hand. The wage
total here is equal to the product of the number of workers employed in
agriculture multiplied by the prevailing wage rate, which roughly corresponds
to the subsistence minimum. It can also quite well be acknowledged that the
current wage rate is above the subsistence level, too. On the one hand, the
entrepreneurs have a relatively large profit margin which allows them to raise
wages; on the other hand, the possibility is quite conceivable that, due to a
shortage of labour, the entrepreneurs will be forced to grant more than the
subsistence minimum as wages in order to be able to employ sufficient workers
at all. Let us note that at this starting point of the development the profit, i.e.
the profit rate is relatively high yet.
We now like to assume that the
population will continue to grow (according to the geometric growth predicted
by Robert Malthus) and that therefore increasingly those soils of poorer
quality will have to be used additionally for cultivation. Since the price of
the soil products must at least cover the unit costs that arise on the
qualitatively poorest soil, the result is an ever-increasing amount of rent
that accrues to the owners of the qualitatively better soil. Of the total
production, the total area below the marginal revenue curve, less and less is
left for profit and wages; and this means that especially the profit rate
decreases, since the wage is anyway largely equivalent to the subsistence
minimum and for these very reasons it cannot be reduced further:
Now we want to ask ourselves whether
there is an end point in this economic development where growth stops and
subsequently remains in a stationary state. The graph shows that once the
population has reached the size B3, the economic development comes to an end.
The profit rate has fallen to zero, the rentiers and the workers share the
total product, whereby the wage rate still corresponds to the subsistence
minimum only. Entrepreneurs and capital providers have no incentive to expand
production, which means that, according to Robert Malthus' pessimistic
population theory, the population expansion can only be stopped by famine or
war.
Let us now turn to David
Ricardo's assessment of this dynamic model and examine the individual
assumptions of this model. The first thing that stands out is that Ricardo, and
with him Robert Malthus of course, only considered the production of
agricultural products. Now, in the initial phase in which the classical theory
was developed, it may have corresponded to reality that agriculture had
accounted for over 90% of total production, so that it seems understandable and
also justified to exclude industrial and manual production from the
consideration in a simple model. We must add, however, that the share of
industrial production increased very fast, so that even during Ricardo's
lifetime this part of the economy could no longer be ignored in an overall
model.
But if we assume that in the
meantime a large part of the production consisted of non-agricultural products,
the question arises whether the law of diminishing revenues, initially
developed only for agriculture and for the production factor soil, can still be
regarded as decisive for the development of the entire national economy. Of
course, the economic development of the entire national economy depends
primarily on the course of revenues in industry, if we must assume that the
major part of the domestic product is produced in industry and craftsmanship.
Despite this circumstance, we
can certainly adopt the revenue development shown by Ricardo. It has in fact
turned out relatively quickly that the regularity observed in the law of
diminishing revenues actually has very little to do with agricultural
production, but rather with the fact that several production factors are
involved in the production of almost all goods, and that for a given technology
there is always an optimum input ratio of these factors. Thus, if only one of
these factors of production, e.g. the labour force, is used more intensively
while the other factors remain constant, the marginal revenue must inevitably
decrease. This means that we can assume that in the area of industrial production,
too, marginal revenues can be expected to decrease.
In this case, however, we have
to modify Ricardo's growth model in the sense that with industrial production,
the scarcity rent no longer accrues to the landowners but to the enterprises,
and that therefore, after deducting the entrepreneurial profit, the remaining
total income must be divided between landowners, capital providers and
employees. However, this makes it unlikely that the profit rate will tend
towards zero.
Ricardo's growth model is
further subject to the criticism that Ricardo has considered insufficiently
that the law of diminishing marginal revenue applies only if the technology of
production remains unchanged. To the extent that technical progress occurs, the
productivity, including the marginal revenue, will increase, with the
consequence that the marginal revenue curve in our diagram will be shifted
outwards, and thus the point of stagnation will be repeatedly shifted into the
future.
De facto, in the course of industrialisation,
production was increased to such an extent that the growth rate of production
soon exceeded the growth rate of the population, thus enabling not only the
domestic product but also - due to an ever-increasing influence of the trade
unions on wage levels - the wage income to be increased.
This trend was intensified by
the fact that the growth rate of the population decreased after a certain point
in time and sometimes even became negative. This development completely contradicts
the pessimistic view of Robert Malthus. It depends on many factors. In the
early stages of industrialisation, a worker needed children so that when he
could no longer work at a certain age, he could be supported by his children
who had grown up in the meantime. As infant mortality was extremely high in the
early stages of industrialisation, a worker could only hope to be supported in
old age if he bore a larger number of children.
This necessity disappeared as
soon as the governments introduced social legislation and therefore the workers
were able to survive materially without material support of their children with
the help of their retirement pension. Infant mortality also declined with
increasing medical progress, so that the desire to have children could be
achieved even with fewer births.
As time went by, the education
of the children became more and more expensive, so that the own children turned
from an initial source of income into a cost factor very soon. This turnaround
has certainly also contributed to the fact that the birth rate declined as
prosperity increased.
Finally, it must be mentioned
in this context that due to the emancipation movement, more and more women
pushed into gainful employment, with the consequence that the desire to have
children was postponed because there was too little time left for bringing up
children.
However, in the most
economically advanced economies, a renewed reversal towards higher birth rates
can be observed. Here, too, several factors are likely to be responsible.
Firstly, the per capita income has often risen so sharply that families can
afford to have children again. In addition, having children often raises social
prestige, especially if one can afford to give the children an excellent
education. Furthermore, more and more states are bearing a considerable part of
the costs associated with bringing up children. This also includes the measures
for the establishment of state-subsidised day care centres for children.
Finally, enterprises are also increasingly willing to open up
career opportunities for women with children by, for example, providing
part-time work also for managers, allowing parents to take their children to an
in-house nursery or eventually allowing parents longer periods of parental
leave.
In summary, we come to similar
conclusions in the assessment of the dynamic model as in the assessment of the
static value model. With his population theory, Robert Malthus correctly
recognised the fundamental problem of every theory of population. He has shown
that poverty can only be overcome if the growth rates of the population and the
domestic product are brought into harmony. Even when his model was based on
partly erroneous assumptions, he provided the impetus for a very fruitful
discussion on population issues.